“… I know this steak doesn't exist. I know that when I put it in my
mouth, the Matrix is telling my brain that it is juicy and delicious. After
nine years, you know what I realize?
… Ignorance is bliss.”
… Ignorance is bliss.”
Cypher, The Matrix.[1]
At the twilight of the twentieth century The Wachowski
Brothers sparked our philosophical imagination by positing a terrible future
that involved a virtual reality that was imposed on humanity by a self-aware
system of complex machinery. Their film, The
Matrix, challenged us to think about what we want our future to be like and
whether is it morally acceptable for us to impose a morally dubious world on
those in the distant future. The Wachowski Brothers’ film also challenges to
think about our obligations to future people and if we have any. One of our
greatest present moral challenges, anthropogenic climate change, is a moral
issue that questions our obligations to future people and their well-being. In
determining our obligations to future people, especially with regards to large
scale and far reaching public and economic policy that affects the environmental
scale of climate change, it can be difficult to see what these obligations are
with respect to their well-being. This essay however, is not an epistemological
argument regarding the validity of anthropogenic climate change theories.[2]
A myriad of peer-reviewed scientific evidence has proven beyond doubt the
causes and consequences of climate change.[3]
Rather, this essay will focus on our moral responsibility to responding to the
human consequences of climate change. This will be done by linking the future
well-being of people with our moral obligations to climate change. Obligations
aside, it is firstly difficult to define what exactly constitutes as well-being
for humans. A substantive and conclusive moral understanding of what well-being
is would be a key component in understanding our obligations to future
generations thus highlighting the morally correct public policy choices that
will safeguard their future well-being.
Defining
well-being has been a difficult exercise for philosophers for thousands of
years; from Aristotle's concept of Eudaimonia
to Jeremy Bentham's unit of pleasure, the hedon.
Tim Mulgan has argued that well-being can not be easily linked exclusively to
either happiness or welfare as this gives rise to objections and intuitively
negative implications.[4]
Happiness has the implication being linked to pleasure; but not all pleasures
are empirically constitutive of what could be regarded as well-being. The
consumption of drugs or alcohol may bring temporary pleasure but overuse will
create negative health effects that most would agree would be detrimental to
well-being. Welfare is unnecessarily tied to material wealth. Monetary value,
although easily measurable, is not explicitly an indicator of well-being
either. A person on a modest income could be a picture of health whereas a
multi-millionaire could over-indulge in fatty foods or suffer from a lack of
meaningful personal social relationships. These do not capture what our
intuition tells us what well-being is. What is constituent of well-being is
what is regarded as intrinsically valuable; a value that is not merely
instrumental for human lives but valuable in itself.[5]
This essay will approach theories of well-being from an rule-utilitarian
perspective. Utilitarianism posits that the correct moral choices are those
that create the greatest happiness for the greatest number, whereas rule-utilitarianism
argues that the correct moral choices are the creation of institutional rules (or
in our case public policy choices) that bring about the greatest happiness for
the greatest number.[6]
Classical
utilitarianism regards hedonism, the presence of pleasure and the absence of
pain, as the only intrinsically valuable constituent of human well-being.[7]
A hedonist public policy would seek to ensure the augmentation of pleasure for
the greatest number. The difficulties hedonism faces are its subjectivity as
well as its phenomenological implications. John Stuart Mill refined Bentham's
original concept of pleasure with higher and lower pleasures.[8]
Mill sought to define higher and lower pleasures with competent judges,
something that immediately manifests thoughts of subjectivity as well as
paternalism. Robert Nozick has argued against a hedonistic view of well-being
by saying pleasure is not the only intrinsically valuable aspect of human
lives. Nozick proposed a thought experiment that speaks to our intuition and
challenges us to reject hedonism. His "Experience Machine", which one
had the choice to plug into or not, consisted of a kind of virtual reality that
was phenomenologically indifferent from reality. Its user could choose any
experience possible from being a successful athlete to completing a great novel.
But the intuitions of those who reject the Experience Machine suggest that
there are more valuable aspects to human experience than purely sensuous
experience. A rejection of the Experience Machine suggests that we need a
greater connection with reality; we want our experiences to be genuine.[9]
Another possible objection to hedonism is similar to the aforementioned
objection to a welfarist, or monetary, conception of well-being. Not all
pleasures are positive: consumption of certain foods, alcohol, or drugs bring
temporally brief sensuous pleasures but in excess would detrimentally affect a
person’s health and therefore well-being. The same could be said of sadistic
pleasures one might acquire from morally objectionable activities such as
torture or rape—psychologically these would be detrimental if they were
regarded to be constituent of well-being.
Nozick, however,
is not rejecting an individual's right to choose the Experience Machine, but is
deferring to an individual the choice rather than insisting the machine as a
hedonist would. This leads us to the second utilitarian conception of
well-being, preference theory, which regards an individual's right to choose
what they prefer as the only intrinsically valuable aspect of human well-being.[10]
The utilitarian approach to preference theory would seek to maximise the
opportunities for preferential moral decisions for the greatest number. This
theory posits that the only morally acceptable way for people to decide
well-being is have them decide for themselves. The theory is popular with libertarians
such as Nozick, because of the emphasis of individual free choice, as well as
economists because it is easily measured—a stronger preference for a resource
or commodity will elicit a higher price therefore show that that particular
item is more preferred for an individual's well-being.[11]
Public policy choices in this regard would cater to an individual's preferences
and thus avoid any accusations of paternalism. Preference theory however faces
similar problems to hedonism: preference is also subjective and can be based on
uninformed choices or ignorance of consequences. Preference theory can also
unfortunately be linked with monetary power and therefore return the measure of
well-being to mere monetary terms rather than something with objective moral
significance; the implication that the preferences of affluent European or
North American choices have more moral worth than those of Latin American or
African choices seems, intuitively, to not grasp the concept of well-being. The
aggressive commodification of all aspects of life in capitalist economies would
have more worth to well-being within preference theory than the
self-sustainability of communal pre-industrial economies because of mere
monetary value—something itself which is instinctively Eurocentric.
The final theory
to be addressed, objective-list, takes a different approach to well-being than
the subjectivism of hedonism and preference theory. Objective-list theory
presupposes a list of items that are intrinsically, as well as objectively,
valuable to human well-being.[12]
These items are based on the independent value of each item rather than a
preference for each item; this creates a desire based on value rather than
value based on desire.[13]
The list might include items such as: healthy food and water; appropriate
clothing and shelter from the elements; positive family and social
relationships; opportunities for education and knowledge; opportunities for
exercise and physical activity; freedom from fear and intimidation; the right
to personal expression. These are just some of the basics that might be
included on a list. Many objectivists might also encompass the above theories
by including positive pleasures and the ability to exercise preferences,
however, these are not the only intrinsically valuable constituents of what
well-being is.
Objective-list
theory relies on empirically measurable proxies for constituent items.[14]
For example, a comprehensive analysis of health would include, but not be
limited to, data concerning rates of disease, mortality, obesity, or mental
illness. A utilitarian approach to objective-list would attempt to augment the
positive aspects in subsequent data for the greatest number, such as lowering
rates of disease or increasing access to healthy food. An advantage
objective-list offers over hedonist and preference theories are that it is less
risk-averse at both an individual and societal level. An adherence to an
objectively measurable standard of well-being is less likely to encounter the
shortcomings of hedonism and preference theory; individuals and societies are
no longer subject to an arbitrary blissful ignorance when it comes to moral
choices concerning their needs. This is especially critical in determining our
moral obligations to future people, more of which will be outlined below.
The obvious
objection objective-list theory immediately faces is accusations of
paternalism. Why should I be told what is good for me? This makes individuals
subject to somebody else’s, often elitist, concept of what well-being is.
Certain individuals might not feel an obligation to adhere to a preconceived
notion of what is good for them; it takes away individuals’ faculties to
rationally choose for themselves what they determine to be adequate for the
well-being of their own lives. Why should an individual not choose Nozick’s
Experience Machine if for them it would make them better off? Objective-list
seems to trample on individual freedoms; something most, if not all, people
value intrinsically, even if some choices may be detrimental. The idea of being
coerced into living a certain way we have been told that it is for our own good
seems, intuitively, to make us anxious. There is also difficulty in determining
what exactly goes on the list and where the list stops; any preconceived list
is inevitably arbitrarily subject to its author’s bias. It might also be less
palatable if the author’s list reflects affluent conceptions of well-being.
Objective-list is just as at risk of accusations of subjectivity as hedonism or
preference theories.
Despite these
objections to an objective conception of well-being it is a more suitable moral
theory for determining our obligations to future people. Subjective theories
breakdown and produce undesirable consequences temporally, especially when
present moral choices drastically affect the well-being of future people. Mulgan
has given more impetus to Nozick’s Experience Machine to demonstrate this; a
further thought experiment called the Virtual Future. Mulgan’s thought
experiment is similar to Nozick’s in the sense that a virtual reality
phenomenologically indifferent to an actual reality is projected onto its user.
Where it differs, is that the Virtual Future is an alternative to a broken
world: a world so damaged by the effects of human activity that it becomes
almost uninhabitable; it is a simultaneously shared user experience within the
virtual world (Mulgan does not mention what portion of the population is
engaged in the Virtual Future machine but it is likely that its use would
elicit a significant expense); every user is aware the reality projected on
them is false but they are also aware that it is preferable to their actual
reality; finally, this is not a reality chosen by its users but imposed on them
by a past generation of people.[15]
To demonstrate
that objective-list theory is the best moral theory regarding both our
obligations of future people as well as our obligations to responses to climate
change Mulgan’s Virtual Future thought experiment could be approached both
literally and metaphorically. Each well-being theory and its implications must
be tested to provoke our intuitive response. A literal interpretation of the
Virtual Future that is not unlike the aforementioned film The Matrix, in the sense that it presupposes that humanity in the
future has indeed somehow destroyed their natural environment beyond repair,
that the technology exists to create (or more disturbingly, impose) an
artificial reality for humanity, and the virtual reality appears to be better
for humanity than the reality of their actual world. The choice faced by a
present generation of people is to decide not for themselves but for their descendants
whether or not to impose this virtual reality on them: a choice between a
broken reality and blissful ignorance. Hedonist and preference theories would
no doubt be useful in providing a better, albeit false, reality for future
generations but distorts what we value phenomenologically. It is forcing us to make
a difficult choice where either option makes us uncomfortable. Our imposition
of a Virtual Future is an easy option to avoid obligations as well as a
disturbing manipulation of the intrinsic values of future generations.[16]
It is another,
metaphorical, interpretation of the Virtual Future thought experiment that
evokes our intuitive reaction to outright dismiss subjective moral theories
regarding obligations to future generations. Mulgan’s thought experiment teases
our train of thought back to the reality of the actual situation humanity
faces: a choice between the imposition of the chaotic effects of climate change
on humanity or a mitigation of these effects to a liveable environment—a
decision that its recipients have to live with but have absolutely no say in
effecting. This is where subjective moral theories break down. There is an
unbridgeable gap between the desires of present people and the desires future
people (it becomes more apparent when subsequent generations no longer overlap
the present generation and as the effects of climate change become increasingly
drastic). If the present generation desires to defer costly responses to
environmental disaster for the sake of economic growth they fail, temporally,
to meet the desires of future generations. Future generations would desire the
same natural environment and all its benefits we enjoy here in the present (or
past) over a destroyed environment especially if they had been given the
choice. It is this imposition where better choices could have been made that
seems morally disturbing in the sense that present choices are both arbitrary
and naïvely authoritarian across time as well as space. Unfortunately, future
people cannot make present decisions and this forces us to rethink our moral
responsibilities in the present to objectively capture what is intrinsically
valuable to well-being across time as well as space. If we think about our list
of objectively valuable items, many of which preference theorists would agree
would contribute to their well-being, it is almost certain that an irrevocably
damaged environment would fail to provide many of these items or a the very
least make them very difficult to provide. Only an application of
objective-list theory is congruent in transmitting what is intrinsically
valuable across time. If we are genuinely concerned about fulfilling the well-being
of future people we must abandon temporally myopic subjective moral theories
that are imposing with regard to our responses to anthropogenic climate change.
The
subjective-objective dichotomy is often contentious in moral philosophy, and
subjective moral theories can certainty accommodate individuality in many
circumstances in the present where present people are affected. But it is this
subjectivity that has dangerous implications when applied to moral decisions
for future people. Subjective moral theories exponentially fail to be
conductive across time. The idea that our moral subjectivity can impose drastic
consequences for future generations is deeply unnerving. Anybody who was born
into undesirable conditions where the decisions regarding those circumstances
were self-regarding (inter-generational rather than inter-personal) expresses
some regret towards their ancestors. If we genuinely believe that it is our
moral obligation to leave future generations better off than the present
generation it is imperative that we adopt an objective account of what human
well-being is. Only then can our present decisions regarding climate change
policy aim to meet the well-being of our descendants without being bogged down
in the myopia of trivial present pursuits.
[1] Joe Pantoliano, The Matrix. Motion picture. Directed by
The Wachowski Brothers. United States: Warner Bros. Pictures, 1999.
[2] For the
purpose of this essay any mention of climate change can be regarded as
anthropogenic i.e. caused by human activity.
[3] Jim Salinger, ed. Living in a Warmer World: How a Changing
Climate Will Affect Our Lives, (Collingwood, Victoria: CSIRO Publishing,
2013), 10-2.
[4] Tim Mulgan, Ethics for a Broken World: Imagining Philosophy After
Catastrophe (Montreal, Québec: McGill-Queen's University Press, 2011), 100.
[5] ibid., 101.
[6] Simon Blackburn, The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), 388.
[7] Roger Crisp. "Well-Being," Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Accessed April 11, 2014,
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/well-being/.
[8] John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism,
On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government, (London, UK:
Everyman's Library, 1984), 10-1.
[9] Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, (New York: Basic
Books, 1974), 42-5.
[10] Mulgan, Ethics for a Broken World, 104.
[11] ibid., 111.
[12] Crisp, “Well-being”.
[13] Mulgan, Ethics for a Broken World,
108.
[14] ibid., 111.
[15] Tim Mulgan, "Ethics for Possible Futures," in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
(London: The Aristotelian Society, 2014), 7-9.
[16] ibid., 10.
———————————————————————————————————————— "... we can explore space together, both inner and outer, forever in peace." —W. M. Hicks.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.